{ "cells": [ { "cell_type": "markdown", "metadata": {}, "source": [ "# Envariance and the Origin of Probabilities in Quantum Mechanics\n", "\n", "This week I'd like to talk about some of Wojciech Zurek's ideas in the foundations of quantum mechanics. \n", "\n", "But first, a word of caution. Philosophically speaking, any time you try to prove something you have to choose a starting place, and the question is whether you can get from A to B. We're going to try to demonstrate how probabilities arise in quantum mechanics, but we're not going to start from scratch: we're going to assume all of unitary quantum mechanics, with its Hilbert spaces, tensor products, entanglements, and so forth. Indeed, Zurek's whole endeavor is to derive Born's rule for probabilities *from* a consideration of the nature of entanglement. In some sense, this could be seen as merely shuffling pieces around the board, substituting one mysterious things for another: e.g., we're not going to explain \"why entanglement\", but instead \"why probabilities given entanglement.\"\n", "\n", "At the same time, there is some justification for this approach. After all, consider the lonely, isolated qubit in a pure state. There is, I think, a very real question about what exactly is \"quantum\" about it at all. A classical spinning object can be defined in terms of its oriented axis of rotation, and the phase of its rotation around that axis: in other words, a point on a sphere, and a point on a circle. And this is exactly, no more and no less, the information encoded in the qubit's state vector.\n", "\n", "We recall: given the state of a qubit quantized along the $Z$ axis, $\\mid \\phi \\rangle = \\begin{pmatrix} \\alpha \\\\ \\beta \\end{pmatrix}$, we can interpret its two complex components as picking out a point on the sphere via $(\\langle \\phi \\mid X \\mid \\phi \\rangle, \\langle \\phi \\mid Y \\mid \\phi \\rangle, \\langle \\phi \\mid Z \\mid \\phi \\rangle)$, or more directly in terms of the complex ratio $\\frac{\\beta}{\\alpha}$, which, stereographically projected from the complex plane to the unit sphere, gives the point on the sphere. (If $\\alpha = 0$, we get end up at the South Pole, the point of projection). \n", "\n", "So in some sense, we're just working with a somewhat unfamiliar complex representation of a point on a sphere plus phase: the ratio between the two components specifies a point on the sphere up to multiplication by a complex number, the latter of which must be a phase (if we've demanded normalization $\\mid \\alpha \\mid^2 + \\mid \\beta \\mid^2 = 1$) which can represent the phase of the rotation around the given axis. (That we're working with a half integer representation of $SU(2)$ is not wholly relevant to the point here.)\n", "\n", "Normally, we'd describe a point on the sphere in terms of cartesian coordinates as a \"superposition\" of basis states: $(1,0,0), (0,1,0), (0,0,1)$, each of which are orthogonal in \"real space\". In our complex representation, it happens that qubit states which are orthogonal complex vectors correspond to antipodal or opposite points on the sphere. So that we can describe a point on the sphere as a complex linear superposition of the vectors corresponding to *any* two opposite points on the sphere. Above, we chose the two points along the $Z$ axis, but any would do. \n", "\n", "So what's quantum about our qubit? The quantum part comes into play only when we consider how the qubit interacts with the world: when it is measured and when it gets entangled: and in some sense, these are the same thing from different perspectives.\n", "\n", "The original logical positivist genius of quantum mechanics was to describe systems as being in linear combinations of states *corresponding to outcomes to experiments*: these orthogonal states can all be encoded as the eigenvectors of some Hermitian operator, whose real eigenvalues correspond to the measured numerical values associated to outcomes (what had been, classically, position, momentum, etc.) The relevant experiment for the qubit is the Stern-Gerlach apparatus: send a spin-$\\frac{1}{2}$ through the magnetic field and it ends up either taking the high road or the low road; and if it takes the high road, it's in the $\\mid \\uparrow \\rangle$ state relative to the Stern-Gerlach axis; and if it takes the down road, it's in the $\\mid \\downarrow \\rangle$ state. So these are the two outcomes: the two outcomes correspond to opposite points on the sphere. Each occurs with a certain probability. How do we get the probability? We describe the state of the qubit as a complex linear superposition $\\alpha \\mid \\uparrow \\rangle + \\beta \\mid \\downarrow \\rangle$, where $\\uparrow$ and $\\downarrow$ are along the axis of the magnetic field, and then the probabilities are given by the norm squared of the amplitudes, $Pr(\\uparrow) = \\mid \\alpha \\mid^2$ and $Pr(\\downarrow) = \\mid \\beta \\mid^2$. This is Born's rule. \n", "\n", "So what we approached first in purely geometrical terms now has this extra probabalistic overlay: what makes the qubit quantum is precisely how it behaves when we interact with it." ] }, { "cell_type": "markdown", "metadata": {}, "source": [ "