{ "cells": [ { "cell_type": "markdown", "metadata": {}, "source": [ "# Quantum Mechanical Puzzles of Supervenience, Pt. II\n", "\n", "First, a brief word on the meaning of the word \"supervenience.\" Wikipedia provides a nice definition:\n", "\n", "\n", "\n", "In other words, to say that mental states \"supervene\" on physical states is to say that there can't be difference in mental states unless there is some corresponding different in physical states. Conversely, if physical states \"supervened\" on mental states, then there couldn't be a difference in physical states unless there was a difference in mental states. Philosophers, of course, differ on how they imagine mind/body interactions to work, whether it's a two way street or one way in one direction or another, or something altogether different. But the point of examining how \"mental states supervene on physical states\" is to ground an account of mentality on physics.\n", "\n", "## More on Bohmian Mechanics\n", "\n", "![bohm0](img/bohm0.png)\n", "\n", "In my mind, Bohmian mechanics is like steampunk physics. Having recourse to wikipedia again, we find steampunk defined as a: \"retrofuturistic subgenre of science fiction that incorporates technology and aesthetic designs inspired by 19th-century industrial steam-powered machinery.\" Indeed, in Bohmian mechanics, we seem to have the revenge of the 19th century: a deterministic theory, in which randomness arises only through ignorance of the initial conditions, and not only that, but a theory which has a thoroughly materialistic ontology, consisting of point particles being buffetted by waves (albeit, satisfying the Schrodinger equation, which is first-order in time), with all higher level properties supervening on these basic elements. And yet, as soon as one looks more closely, the theory is really more like 19th century physics on an acid trip. To reproduce the predictions of quantum mechanics, the theory must be wildly nonlocal, the velocities of the particles depending on the entire rest of the world at a given moment, which in itself is unsettling, but for that matter conflicts with special relativity (although such violations would not necessarily be apparent, given that we're generally ignorant of the real locations of the particles). Depending on one's prejudices, however, this may be a feature: even as there was something comforting about the 19th century deterministic world, unfolding inevitably according to a grand plan imposed at the beginning by some God-given initial conditions, the old classical physics was depressingly insistent that, insofar as we're spatially separate configurations of atoms and fields, we are all metaphysically \"alone.\" In contrast, in Bohmian mechanics, everything is connected to everything else so intimately that my thoughts could literally be determining your thoughts right now, with no intermediate step, and with *cosmic inevitability*. \n", "\n", "But an even subtler feature is the contextuality of all observables other than position in Bohmian mechanics. As we've seen, if we send a particle surfing on a wavefunction in a superposition of spin $\\uparrow$ and $\\downarrow$ through a measuring device, the port at which the particle exits depends on whether the particle happened to be above or below the midpoint of the device: and consequently, if the device were flipped over, the particle would exit the opposite port, in other words, it would exit out the $\\downarrow$ port instead of the $\\uparrow$ port, even though nothing had changed with regard to the particle or its wavefunction. In other words, the measured value of the spin depends on the spatial context: exactly how the particle happens to be located relative to the device, exactly how the device is oriented, and so forth. Now there's nothing objectionable about a theory in which higher level properties bottom out at something more fundamental: observables in classical physics basically bottom out at the positions and momenta of the underlying particles. But here, the issue is that the measurable aspects of higher level properties seem to depend on something *semantically irrelevant*. In normal quantum mechanics, we can assign a sensible semantics to the spin part of a wavefunction, to its position part, and so forth. And even if the spin and the position can get entangled, they have a semantic identitity of their own. But in Bohmian mechanics, the outcome of spin measurements depends seemingly irrelevantly on how the apparatus is positioned relative to the point particle, so that the concept of spin itself can't be separated from the spatial configuration. And not just spin, but any observable property other than position in standard Bohmian mechanics is contextual in just this way, inevitably depending on contigencies which make it impossible to regard those properties as having any semantic meaning on their own.\n", "\n", "Now you could bite the bullet and say, Well, that's just how it is! Get used to it! Contextuality sounds strange, but surely it's better than accepting that the outcome is literally random! At least, there *is* a reason, even if it's inherently, by definition, unsatisfying.\n", "\n", "But consider than actually Bohmian mechanics isn't unique, and that actually there's an infinitude of equally good such theories, each of which reproduces the predictions of quantum mechanics, but which radically disagree about what are the particles and what are the trajectories. What do I mean?\n", "\n", "Well, you might wonder, first of all, could we formulate Bohmian mechanics *in the momentum representation*? In other words, in the standard formulation, the position wavefunction is regarded as a \"really existing\" guiding wave, which tells point particles, specified by a list of positions, how to move. But what if instead you worked with the momentum wavefunction, regarded as a \"really existing\" guiding wave (in momentum space!), which tells point particles (specified by a list of momenta!), how to move? In fact, the physicist Epstein suggested this to Bohm even back in the 50's, and while there were originally some technical issues, recent work has shown that this is perfectly coherent. You'll end up with a deterministic, contextual theory, where everything supervenes on momenta, where momentum particles take definite momentum trajectories through momentum space, and all of it adds up to standard quantum mechanics, just as in the usual Bohmian theory. Moreover, there's a way of definining such momentum trajectories in the usual position-based theory, and a way of defining position trajectories in the momentum-based theory: and they disagree! And yet, they both add up to standard quantum mechanics. \n", "\n", "For that matter, why not choose a basis in between position and momentum? Do a fractional Fourier transform, and repeat the construction. You'll get a new deterministic ontology, where everything supervenes contextually, and which reproduces quantum mechanics. And in fact, you could choose any continuous basis you like! \n", "\n", "You could even use a coherent state basis, parameterized by position *and* momentum, in other words, where the state is decomposed into an infinitude of displaced Gaussians, and then you'd have Bohmian mechanics *on phase space*, where a guiding wave in phase space pushes phase space points around, and everything supervenes contextually atop that.\n", "\n", "